In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts
Second Reader: Assistant Professor Anna Loutfi
Abstract
This thesis examines the concept of anthropological machine introduced by political
philosopher Giorgio Agamben. Through a close reading of his work The Open: Man andAnimal I define anthropological machine as an assemblage of sciences about human biology,
technologies that target human biological life and the attitude to human biological life as to
the entity that can be managed and controlled. Turning to the theories of Rosi Braidotti,
Donna Haraway and Francis Fukuyama I examine what meaning to science and technology
they ascribe in their philosophy. I conclude that in a biopolitical state, where human life
becomes a commodity and a part of social, economic and trade relations, science and
technology have the capacity not only for the mere management of human biology, but also
for the reconfiguration of what constitutes for the human and what stands for the non-human. Acknowledgments
I would like to thank my supervisor professor Allaine Cerwonka for the insightful comments,
patient guidance and inspiration that she gave to me throughout my work on this project. I
feel extremely privileged that I had a chance to work under her supervision and to take the
courses she offered in the academic year of 2011/2012.
I also want to express my gratitude to professors Anna Loutfi and Eszter Timar for
intellectually stimulating classes and extremely helpful comments that they gave on my
This work is dedicated to my parents whose most gentle care and support gave me strength to
Table of Contents
Introduction
In this work I examine how various political and social thinkers of the present address
the role of machines and technologies in a biopolitical state. Biopolitics addresses human
biological life (Lemke 2011, p. 2), the kind of life that Italian political philosopher Giorgio
Agamben (2002) calls nutritive or animal life (p. 14-15). In a contemporary biopolitical state
human biological life is managed by the means of biomedical technology (Rose 2007, p. 3).
In The Open: Man and Animal Agamben (2002) introduces the concept of anthropological
machine to discuss how human biology is targeted by natural and medical sciences and how
it can be managed by technologies. In my thesis I take Agamben's understanding of the
machine as an assemblage of medical and natural sciences and biomedical technologies and
explore how other social and political thinkers address the problem of sciences and
technologies' grip of human biological life.
In Chapter 1 I offer a close reading of The Open: Man and Animal and discuss why in
Agamben's philosophy the machine has a complex meaning of the combination of sciences
and technologies. Moreover, I examine the connotation that Agamben associates with the
concept of the machine. Thus, I argue that in Agamben's theory the image of the machine
renders the idea of science and technology being an artificial, strange to the living world
entity that reduces the life of its complexity and mystery (Oliver 2009, p. 234-235).
In chapter 2 turn to the theories of feminist thinkers Donna Haraway (2004; 2008) and
Rosie Braidotti (2002). Along with Agamben, Haraway and Braidotti engage with the
question of how sciences bring into close proximity the human to the animal and how
technology intervenes into human body. However, while Agamben represents sciences and
technologies that they produce with an image of the machine that poses threat to the human-
being, Haraway and Braidotti observe positive sides in the destruction of the boundaries
between the human and the non-human. Haraway's cyborg or Braidotti’s nomad, the subjects
that emerge when the borders between the human, the animal and the machine are
transcended, in Haraway's (2004; 2008) and Braidotti's (2002) vision, are capable of
producing a new kind of politics. Since the animal, along with women or colonized people,
is one of the facets of modernity's Other, opposed to the dominant Self, cyborg and nomadic
subjects open the possibility for the emergence of the society without hierarchies, oppositions
and domination (Styhre 2001, pp. 4-5). However, by applying cyborg or nomadic identities to
surrogate motherhood, I challenge Haraway's and Braidotti's idea about the egalitarian
politics that cyborg and nomad produce. Turning to Achille Mbembe's (2008) theory I draw
parallels between surrogate mothers, slaves and such machines as labor saving devices, and
claim that while in Mbembe's (2008) theory slavery is “an instance of a biopolitical
experimentation” (p. 160), and slave is what Agamben (2002) names bare life, human with
suspended humanity, surrogacy can also be considered as an example of biopolitical
experimentation, and surrogate mothers can be regarded as bare life. That said, surrogacy
becomes an example of Agamben's anthropological machine at work, as in the case of
surrogacy biomedical technologies target human biological functions and reduce the human
In Chapter 2 I emphasize the fact that Haraway (2004; 2008) and Braidotti (2002) fail
to take into consideration the unequal access to biomedical technologies when they praise the
erasure of the borders between the human, the machine and the animal and the intervention of
technology into human body. In Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology
Francis Fukuyama appeals to the empirical research and demonstrates how biomedical
technologies are not equally accessible by people. In Fukuyama's (2002) theory such an
uneven distribution of biomedical technologies is the reason why he calls politics, philosophy
and religion to control how science and biomedical technologies put human biological life at
stake of social, economic and trade relations. Like Agamben (2002), Fukuyama (2002)
considers technology's management of human biological life to be the consequence of the
reduction of the distance between the human and the animal that natural and medical sciences
do. According to Fukuyama (2002), in order to stop the reduction of the human to mere
biological functions, human exceptionality and uniqueness should not be contested by
science, and the notion of the human should be taken for granted. At first glance, Fukuyama's
idea to set definite boundaries of the human and not to question human difference from other
species may sound like a call to stop the operation of anthropological machine, which
dehumanizes the human. However, I argue, that Fukuyama's idea of taking the notion of the
human for granted may actually contribute to the dehumanization of certain groups of people
who can be pushed outside the boundaries of the human. I will support this claim by the fact
that in Fukuyama's theory the breaching of the borders between the human and the non-
human is something that has the potential to happen in future. Meanwhile, the case of
surrogacy serves as an example of how the borders of the human and the non-human are
already being transgressed, and the introduction of fixed definition of what is human can
dehumanize those whose subjectivities exist in-between the human, the machine and the
My overall argument is that Agamben's anthropological machine is a succinct
metaphor that describes how natural and medical sciences and biomedical technologies that
flourish in contemporary highly medicalized society (Rose 2007, p. 1) are capable to
reconfigure the meaning of the human due to their capacity of reducing the distance between
the human, the animal and the machine. Chapter 1 Anthropological Machine: Reconfiguration of the Human and the Animal 1.1 Introduction
In this chapter I argue that in Giorgio Agamben’s theory anthropological machine has
a range of meanings. Oliver (2009) writes that the notion of the machine represents a
combination of various discourses among which scientific discourse is the predominant one
(p. 229, p. 234). Since it is mainly natural and medical sciences that operate anthropologicalmachine, and, hence, draw a division between the human and the animal, in Agamben’s
theory machine functions as a metaphor that reflects how medical and natural sciences situate
zoe, the animal, within the human and produce a mechanistic division of the human on social
and biological, on the human and the animal.
Along with that, I claim, that in his theory Agamben also addresses the role of
machines in a direct, non-metaphorical meaning of this word: I argue that, although not
utterly explicitly, Agamben offers us an insight into the fact that machines and technology
produced by natural and medical sciences are capable of reducing the human to the animal.
Following Oliver’s (2009) interpretation of Agamben’s hint on the capacity of technology to
animalize the human, I claim that in Agamben’s theory medical machines and technology
animalize the human by the fact that they objectify human being.
While in my interpretation, the machine in Agamben’s philosophy stands for natural
and medical sciences and technologies they produce that altogether target human biological
life, I also want to point out a strong negative and menacing connotation with which
Agamben fills his concept of the machine. I find it striking that Agamben uses machine, the
third element of the triangle of human-animal-machine to analyze how the animal gets
opposed to the human, and how at the same time animal can be situated within the human and
can be targeted by state powers. From my analysis of the work that the concept of
anthropological machine does in Agamben’s philosophy, I infer that Agamben uses this very
concept to communicate the idea of some artificial, mechanistic and rational entity that
meddles into the living world and decides on what kind of life is politically relevant and what
kind of life is not, what sort of life may constitute for bios and what sort of life can constitute
for zoe, what type of life is human and what type of life is animal.
Said that, I assume that the machine in Agamben’s theory stands for the assemblage of
certain kinds of scientific knowledge about the human that produce certain kinds of
technologies that target human biological life and that entail certain attitude to human
biological life. Such a reading of Agamben’s concept of anthropological machine resonates
with the meaning that Nicolas Rose (2007), social scientist and a theorist of biopolitics,
ascribes to the notion of technologies of life. From Rose’s (2007) perspective, in biopolitical
theory the meaning of technology does not simply boil down to equipment or techniques (p.
16). In Rose’s (2007) theory technology of life encompasses “knowledges, instruments,
persons, systems of judgment, buildings and spaces, underpinned at the programmatic level
by certain presuppositions and assumptions about human beings.” (p. 17)
Rose (2007) observes that the presence of biomedical technologies in our life makes
us to rethink the ownership of our body and the meaning of our biological life: he highlights
that human body and life become engaged in trade and social relations, and becomes a
commodity (p. 17). In his analysis of how sciences situate the animal within the human,
Agamben (2002) also hints on the fact that the situation of animality by natural and medical
sciences, and the existence of technologies that these very sciences produce create the
possibility for human physiology to become the ends of human social and economic relations
I assume that the striking peculiarity of the notion of Agamben’s anthropologicalmachine consists not only in the fact that it is a concept with such a multi-layered meaning,
but also in the fact that it differs Agamben’s theory on biopolitics from the works of other
thinkers who engaged with the topic of biopolitics, such Achille Mbembe, Roberto Esposito,
In Homo Sacer and The Open: Man and Animal Agamben engages with the question
of how the state exercises its power on human life. When saying that in modernity human
biological life becomes the object on which the state exercises its power, Giorgio Agamben
follows to a great extent Michel Foucault (2003) who describes biopolitics as state’s control
over the biological life of population. Thus, Agamben (1998) discusses the notion of
biopolitics that he defines, following Foucault (2003), as the kind of politics at which “the
species and the individual as a simple living body become what is at stake in a society’s
political strategies” (p. 3) and “nation’s health and biological life become a problem of
Thus, although in his theory Agamben, like Foucault (2003), analyzes how human
biological life becomes the target of modern politics, in The Open: Man and Animal he,
however, adds the concept of anthropological machine as a new analytical tool to reveal the
mechanisms that make human biological life a political concern and to express his anxiety
about the reduction of the human to the animal and the consequences that this reduction can
To support my argument about the significance of the notion of the machine for the
understanding of Agamben’s theory on biopolitics and to discuss all the meanings that this
notion embraces, I will, firstly examine how Agamben represents the role of natural and
medical sciences in the work of anthropological machine, and hence, in the production of the
human and the animal. Secondly, I will discuss how Agamben envisages the role of machines
and technology in the mediation of the relation between the human and the animal. Thirdly, I
will discuss what sort of connotation the image of machine possesses in Agamben’s
philosophy, and how it reveals Agamben’s anxiety about the process of the animalization of
the human performed by sciences and technology. 1.2 Science: the situation of the animal within the human
In his discussion of how the human has been opposed to the animal and how the
animal was situated within the human, Agamben discusses how various disciplines, such as
theology, philosophy and natural and medical sciences were engaged in the production of the
opposition between the human and the animal. However, in her reading of The Open: Manand Animal Oliver (2009) observes that Agamben ascribes an important role to science when
he describes the work of anthropological machine: according to her, in anthropologicalmachine Western science decreases the gap between the human and the animal, and, hence,
Indeed, a close reading of Agamben’s The Open: Man and Animal reveals his keen
interest in the way medical and natural sciences are engaged in the work of anthropologicalmachine and its side effect of the animalization of the human. Thereby, in his analysis of
how biological life becomes the target of modern politics, Agamben equals human biological
life to animal life, building his equation on the work of Aristotle and French anatomist and
physiologist Marie-Francois Xavier Bichat, whose work, according to Agamben (2002),
implies that “something like an animal life can be separated within man”. (p. 15.)
Having the most important place in the work of Agamben’s anthropological machine,
medical and natural sciences, however, seem to interlace with other disciplines. Thus, for
instance, Agamben (2002) writes that Aristotle's isolation of zoe, that is nutritive life and that
is responsible for nutrition, decay and growth (p. 13-14) and is shared by all living beings
and the contrasting of zoe to bios, political and relational life, that is inherent in people, is a
“fundamental event for Western science” (Agamben 2002, p. 14). In Agamben’s analysis,
Aristotle’s idea of zoe and bios is crucial for the development of Western science, such as
biology and medicine and how these sciences inherent a lot from this philosophical idea in
the way they define the human and the animal, Agamben turns to the work of French
anatomist and physiologist Marie-Francois-Xavier Bichat.
According to Agamben (2002), in the 18th century Marie-Francois- Xavier Bichat
drew a distinction between 'animal life' and 'organic life', situating within higher organisms
l'animal existant au-dedans and l'animal existant au-dehors. Agamben (2002) explains that
for Bichat l'animal existant au-dedans is responsible for organic functions, such as blood
circulation and respiration (p. 15), while l'animal existant au-dehors “is defined through its
relation to the external world” (Agamben 2002, p. 15). In Absolute Immanence Agamben
(1999) writes that in Bichat's distinction between l'animal existant au-dedans and l'animalexistant au-dehors “it is still Aristotle's nutritive life that constitutes the background against
which the life of superior animals is separated and on which the “animal living on the
outside” is opposed to the animal on the inside” (p. 231).
Agamben (2002) writes that Aristotle's idea of the existence of two kinds of life that
higher organisms have, zoe and bios, and Bichat's similar idea about two animals inhabiting
the human and being responsible for two different sets of life functions, is still present in
contemporary times. Thus, firstly, he writes that in Western culture the human is “thought of
as the articulation of a body and a soul, of a living thing and logos, of a natural (animal)
element and a supernatural or social, divine element” (Agamben 2002, p. 16). Apart from
influencing our general vision of the human as a mixture of animality and humanity, of
terrestrial and celestial, Agamben (2002) writes that Aristotle's and later Bichat's division of
life functions on nutritive and relational is of great importance for modern surgery and
anesthesia that are based on this distinction between two kinds of life functions (p. 15).
When tracing how Aristotle's and Bichat's ideas about two kinds of life are present in our
society, Agamben (2002) writes that what, according to Foucault is at stake in a biopolitical
state, is nothing but that zoe situated by Aristotle or l'animal existant au-dedans, identified by
Thereby, Agamben demonstrates how the idea of duality of the human, fuels
anthropological machine to dissect the human on the animal and the human, on biological
and social, on flesh and consciousness, and how the animal, the biological and the flesh
In Agamben's theory the fact that Bichat, following Aristotle, said that humans share
basic organic functions with animals is an example of how scientific inquiry about human
biology lays in the basis if the work of anthropological machine: Agamben's (2002) reference
to Bichat's work illustrates how science is engaged in the breaching of the boundaries
between the human and the animal by situating animality within the human.
Another reference to science that Agamben (2002) makes to demonstrate that it is a
scientific discourse that is predominant in the work of anthropological machine and its side-
effect, the animalization of the human, is his reference to the work of Swedish naturalist Carl
Linnaeus (p. 23). Agamben (2002) writes that Linnaeus' claim about the difficulty of
identifying specific difference between apes and the human tells us about the uncertainty of
the boundaries between the human and the animal.
Combining Aristotle's and Bichat's idea of the existence of animality within the
human with the struggle of the scholars of the Enlightenment period to find distinctive
features of the human versus animal, Agamben (2002) concludes that “Homo sapiens, then, is
neither a clearly defined species nor a substance; it is, rather, a machine or device for
producing the recognition of the human” (p. 26). Agamben (2002) writes that when the
human looks at himself, his image is 'deformed in the features of an ape” (p. 27). Here, I
assume that Agamben wants to communicate two things. The first thing is that natural
sciences have created the tradition of defining the human by comparing it to the animal. The
second thing is that this comparison implies simultaneous contrasting of the human to the
animal and defining some features shared by both the human and the animal. Thus, in
Agamben’s theory, natural and life sciences serve as crucially important operative mechanism
of anthropological machine (Agamben 2002, p. 37).
Oliver (2009) agrees that Agamben's anthropological machine is 'fueled' by science
(p. 234). According to her, in Agamben's theory it is biological and medical science that
breaches the borders between the human and the animal, and, eventually, reduces the human
to the animal (p. 234). Thus, I assume, in Agamben's philosophy biological and medical
science are represented as standing above the human and the animal and mediating both the
meanings of these categories and their interrelation.
Thus, in Agamben's theory anthropological machine that is operated mainly by natural
science, not only mechanistically divides life on animal and human life, but also creates the
hierarchical relations between animal and human life. Since the nutritive life or l'animalexistant au dedans are shared by all the living organisms, and relational life or l'animalexistant au-dehors is inherent only in humans, the isolation of nutritive life or l'animalexistant au-dedans to relational life or l'animal existant au dehors implies the establishing of
hierarchy living organisms with those having relational life occupying the top of the
hierarchy. The fact that in Agamben's theory natural and life sciences mediate the relations
between zoe and bios by producing a taxonomic view on living species, dividing them on
higher and less developed, on those who possess relational life and on those who lack it, will
be useful in Chapter 2 of my thesis, in which I will turn to the works of Braidotti (2002) and
Haraway (2004; 2008), and will examine what role in mediating relations between the human
and the animal they ascribe to machines.
In this section I have examined how natural and medical science act as dominant
forces in the operation of anthropological machine and draw the line between the human and
the animal, and, at the same time, situate animal life within the human. In this sense machine,
fuelled mainly by natural and medical science, metaphorically dissects the human on such
opposite categories as the biological and the social, the animal and the human. However,
further in this chapter, I will consider how technology and machines in the direct meaning of
this word are engaged in the work of anthropological machine, and how in Agamben’s theory
they have the capacity to reduce the human to the animal. 1.3 Technological grip of human life
When saying that the result of the work of anthropological machine is the
animalization of the human (Agamben 2002, p. 37), and that human biological life “becomes
the supreme political task” (Agamben 2002, p. 76), Agamben’s claim resembles Foucault's
(2003 characterization of biopolitics as the application of state power to man as to living
species (p. 243). Meanwhile, unlike Foucault, Agamben (2002) not only uses the image of
anthropological machine that, as I assume, in his theory represents natural science, medicine
and technology, but he also introduces the concept of bare life to describe the human whose
humanity is suspended and depends on the work of anthropological machine (Puchner 2007,
Bare life is situated in-between relational, political life and mere biological life that is
shared by all living organisms. Thus, bare life has the potential of becoming human life or
animal life, and, hence the category of the human and non-human “can be decided upon and
produced.” (Agamben 2002, p. 21). As I have proved in the previous part of this chapter, it is
mainly natural and medical sciences that operate the work of the anthropological machine,
and, hence, in Agamben’s theory natural and medical sciences take a great part in the
production of bare life and in the decision upon bare life’s humanity or animality.
However, along with the fact that the machine in Agamben’s theory stands for life
sciences, natural sciences and medicine that, so to say, dissect the human on the human and
the animal, it is, I assume, rather legitimate to claim that in Agamben’s theory, machine can
Agamben (2002) writes that post-historical man aims at governing his animality by
the means of technology (p. 80). Oliver (2009) elaborates on Agamben’s vision of the state
management of human biological life through technology and says that in contemporary
world, machines play an important role in the management of human biological life. She
writes that contemporary medicine is full of machine and computer metaphors that depict the
work of human body, especially, human brain (Oliver 2009, p. 236). According to Oliver
(2009) the mechanization of life, that is typical of our time of machines and technology, adds
Taking on Agamben’s (2002) idea of the “total management of life” by the means of
technology (p. 77), Oliver (2009) writes that such practices that involve special medical
technology and equipment, as human cloning and transplantation reduce the human to the
animal (p. 237). She supports this argument by saying that the application of the
aforementioned medical practices to the human resembles the way that animals are subjected
to automated processing by factory farming, mechanized slaughter and meatpacking (Oliver
2009, p. 237). Thus, Oliver asserts that technical, mechanic, aspect of modern medicine and
life sciences, takes the grip of human biological life and strips humans of their humanity.
Oliver (2009) argues that factory farms and slaughterhouses are the models for the
concentration camp, which in Agamben’s theory is an exemplary space of biopolitics
(Agamben 1998, p. 4) (p. 231). However, judging from Oliver’s (2009) idea of human
cloning and transplantation being an example of how technology takes a grip of human
biological life, I think, it can be said that the medical laboratory and the operating room are
also spaces of contemporary biopolitics. As Oliver (2009) claims, medical laboratories and
operating rooms are the space, where human biological life is objectified, manipulated and
altered by the means of medical technology and devices, and, in this, sense, Oliver (2009),
writes that there is no significant difference between mechanic butchering, milking and
packaging of animals for consumption and human cloning and organ transplantation.
Thereby, elaborating on Agamben’s (2002) idea of technology governing human
animality (p. 77), Oliver (2009) discusses how life and medical sciences by the means of the
application of medical devices to human body, breach the boundary between the human and
the animal through the animalization of the human. Thus, human cloning and organ
transplantation are scientific practices that operate the work of modern anthropologicalmachine, by the animalization of the human. Notably, human cloning and organ
transplantation are practices impossible without special medical devices and technology and,
hence, in this case, the animalization of the human is literally done through the usage of
While Agamben (2002) says that the essence of the work of anthropological machine
of modernity is the animalization of the human, in the end of The Open: Man and Animal,
Agamben (2002) writes that there is a possibility for the emergence of a new sort of life, that
is neither the animal and the human, when he discusses the mastery of the life by the means
of technology. He does not elaborate further on his suggestion of technology being capable of
not only animalization of the human and manipulation of human biology, but also giving a
chance for a new type of life to emerge. Thus, Wadiwel (2004) observes, that Agamben
(2009) touches the topic of non-humans, including animals as well as machines, having the
potential for the reconfiguration of the category of the human (p. 7) According to Wadiwel
(2004), Agamben could use the works of Donna Haraway and Bruno Latour to discuss this
Instead of engaging with the question of the potential that machines have to
reconfigure the relations of the human and the animal, Agamben (2002) rather succinctly
outlines two possible scenarios of the work of anthropological machine. Thus, he writes that,
the first scenario, involves further production of the opposition between the human and the
animal, and the situation of the animality within the human and its control by the means of
science and technology (Agamben 2002, p. 80). In the second scenario, suggested by
Agamben (2002), “the animality is neither hidden nor is made an object of mastery, but is
thought as such” (p. 80). In other words, in the work of the second scenario of
anthropological machine the human and the animal are no longer opposed to each other in
the way where animal is inferior to the human (Agamben 2002, p. 92).
According to Oliver (2009), the introduction of machines into our life makes it
possible for the unfolding of the second scenario. (p. 237). She argues that with the advent of
machines can fuel the analysis of the categories of living and machine, instead of human and
animal (Oliver 2009, p. 237). In Chapter 2 of my thesis I will take on Oliver’s idea of
machines having the capacity to challenge the hierarchical dichotomy of the human and the
animal, and will turn to the works of Donna Haraway (2004; 2008), whose scholarship, as
Wadiwel writes, Agamben could use to elaborate further on the question of how machines
change the relations between humanity and animality. Along with Haraway’s scholarship I
will also use the works by Rosi Braidotti (2002). 1.4 Religion, Science and the Borders of the Human Community
In the previous sections of this chapter I have analyzed how Agamben considers natural
and medical sciences to be the tool for the breaching of the boundary between the human and the
animal. In his theory natural and medical sciences identify common features between the human
and bring the animal and the human into such a close proximity that it leads to the animalization
of the human, and the emergence of what Agamben (2002) names bare life: the human whose
humanity can be suspended (p. 38). Thus, Agamben (2002) points out at the obvious dependency
of the existence of the human with suspended humanity on the scientific knowledge that claims
that there is not much difference between the human and the animal. Oliver (2009) writes that “a
bare life is one produced by biological and medical science as a living body separated from its
social, political and even ecological context. It is an exceptional body (monstrous or sacred)
whose fate can be determined outside systems of law or reason.”
The capacity of anthropological machine that operates with a rather significant
contribution of natural and medical science, to produce the human that can be stripped of is
humanity charges Agamben's notion of the machine with a significant amount of anxiety.
Oliver (2009) claims that in Agamben's philosophy the threat that medical and natural
sciences and technology pose constitutes in the fact that they deprive the world of its mystery
“under the searing gaze of science” (p. 234). Agamben (2002) calls for philosophy and
theology to intervene into the process of the articulation of the meanings of the human and
the animal that in his theory is performed mostly by medical and natural sciences (p. 22).
Agamben's anxiety about science being the dominant tool for the moving of the caesura
between the human and the animal is also expressed in the fact that he addresses
concentration and extermination camps as the examples of places where the notions of the
human and the animal are collapsed due to the fragility and uncertainty of the line between
these two categories (Agamben 2002, p. 22). He underlines the monstrosity of the
phenomenon of the concentration and extermination camp (Agamben 2002, p. 22).
Meanwhile, the concentration and the extermination camps are the spaces of biopolitics
(Agamben 1998, p. 169 ), where, like in any biopolitical space, medical sciences acquire the
power to decide on the humanity of the human. From this definition of the concentration
camp, I assume, it is possible to infer that in Agamben's theory the concentration camp is the
place where the work of the anthropological machine is represented at its most vivid form.
Keeping in mind the fact that it is medical and natural sciences that are the dominant
forces that operate the work of the machine, it is evident that Agamben regards science as a
potential threat to the stability of the borders of the human. His appeal to philosophy and
theology to intervene into the animalization of the human that science does, resonates with
Campbell's (2008) description of Derrida's concept of religious immunity (p. xv). Campbell
(2008) writes that in Derrida's philosophy “religious immunity lies in the distinction between
bio-zoological or anthropo-theological lie and transcendental, sacred life” (p. xv). Campbell
(2008) adds that “if there is a biopolitical moment to be found in Derrida's analysis of
religion and autoimmunity, it will be found here in the difference between biological life and
transcendental life that will continually require the difference between the two to be
Said that, I assume that Agamben’s call for philosophy and theology to interfere into the
animalization of the human that is done by medical and natural sciences, may be interpreted as
an idea of religious immunization of the human, whose borders are threatened to be blurred by
science with the boundaries of the bio-zoological world of the animal. Thus, Agamben calls for
humanities, non-natural science knowledge to protect the fragile borders of the human.
I will examine a similar sentiment about the capacity of religion to stop the animalization
of the human, and to foster the boundaries of the human community against sciences capacity to
breach the boundaries between the human and non-human in Francis Fukuyama's theory in
1.5 Conclusion
In this chapter I argued that Agamben's concept of anthropological machine has a
range of meanings. Thus, the notion of anthropological machine implies natural and medical
sciences that by identifying the similarities between the human and the animal, deprive the
human of the feeling of self-uniqueness; it also includes technologies that target human
biological life and, eventually, it implies a certain attitude to human biological life, - which
means that human biology is perceived as manageable by the intervention of sciences and
technologies. I also concluded that Agamben's concept of anthropological machine has a
rather menacing connotation, as Agamben regards science as a potential danger for human
dignity, and that is why his call for theology to stop the animalization of the human can be
interpreted as an idea of religious immunization of the integrity of the borders of the human. Chapter 2 Machines in Feminist Perspective (Haraway, Braidotti) 2. 1 Introduction
In Chapter 1 of my thesis I discussed the meaning of the concept of machine in
Agamben's philosophy. I concluded that in Agamben's theory machine has a multi-faceted
meaning: on the one hand, it is a combination of different discourses, among which the
scientific discourse is the dominant one, and this combination of discourses produces the
binary opposition of the animal and the human, and situates animality within the human. On
the other hand, machine in Agamben's theory can be understood in a more direct sense of this
word. Machines are equipment and technology by the means of which human biological life
In this chapter I turn to the theories of Donna Haraway (2004; 2008) and Rosie
Braidotti (2002) who also engage in the discussion of the way scientific inquiries, especially
in the realm of natural and medical sciences, breach the boundary between the human and the
non-human. They agree on the fact that science undoes human's sense of exceptionality by
bringing the human to close proximity with the animal and, hence, by making the boundary
between the human and the non-human fragile.
When Haraway (2008) discusses how science can shake human self-certainty, she
refers to Freud who describes three scientific inquiries that challenged the idea of human
superiority (p. 11-12). She writes that the first scientific idea that inflicted a 'wound to the
primary narcissism of the self-centered human subject' (Haraway 2008, p. 11) is Copernicus'
idea about the Earth not being the center of the universe, that opened for the humanity the
cosmos, a new unexplored abyss, probably inhabited by other, unknown organisms. The
second 'wound' to human exceptionality that Haraway (2008) discusses is Darwin's theory of
evolution: it put the human in one order with the animals and did not provide any guarantee
that the human is the culmination, the acme of the development of living organisms (p. 11).
The third 'wound' that Haraway (2008) mentions is Freud's undoing of “the primacy of
conscious processes” (p. 11). Haraway (2008) writes that with his theory of unconscious
Freud challenged human rationality and reason, features that distinguish the human from
other species and, hence, serve as an argument in favor of human exceptionality (p. 12). She
concludes that it is science that contributed to shifting the human from the center of the
universe, and it is science that breaches the so-called great divide between the human and the
Braidotti (2002) also mentions the fact that science brings in close proximity the
human and the non-human. Referring to Deleuze and Guattari's essay Becoming-Intense,Becoming-Animal, Becoming-Imperceptible from “A Thousand Plateaus”, Braidotti (2002)
writes that “evolutionary theory and genetics; psychoanalysis, which simultaneous unveils
and disavows the 'beast within' and the long tradition of literary representation of animals” (p.
12) created the discourse that reduces the distance between the human and the animal.
Braidotti's and Haraway's appraisal of the role of science in challenging of the
meaning of the human echoes with Agamben's analysis of science's animalization of the
human is a sense that Braidotti, Haraway and Agamben position science as a tool by the
means of which the uniqueness of the human is challenged. In Agamben's (2002) theory such
scientific inquiries as Tyson's work on comparative anatomy of the human and the ape, and
Bichat's division of human life functions on nutritive and relational, on flesh and
consciousness became the foundation for the operation of anthropological machine and its
side-effect, the animalization of the human. In Haraway's and Braidotti's theories science
plays as an important role in blurring of the boundaries between the human and the non-
human, as natural and medical sciences that contribute to the operation of Agamben's (2002)
anthropological machine and situate the animality, within the humans themselves.
However, Agamben's (2002) attitude to science as a tool for the breaching of the
boundaries between the human and the non-human is significantly different from those of
Haraway and Braidotti In chapter 1, I discussed that there is a lot of anxiety in Agamben's
(2002) image of anthropological machine. In Agamben's theory anthropological machine
serves as a powerful image of artificial, rational, menacing entity that is fuelled by medical
and natural sciences, destroys human integrity by drawing mechanistic division of human life
on zoe and bios, and that, ultimately, deprives the human of its mystery, exceptionality and
processes it into bare biological life. Besides, there is a certain amount of anxiety about the
potential of technology to get the grip on human biological life (Agamben 2002, p. 77).
Thereby, in Agamben's (2002) thought machine is, on the one hand, a menacing metaphor of
natural and medical sciences reducing the human to the animal. On the other hand,
Agamben's (2002) machine is a no less an intimidating image of technology itself that is
capable of inflicting as much harm to the human being as sciences can by revealing human’s
animality and making it the object of management.
In their analysis of how various branches of sciences and the technologies that they
produce get introduced in our life, Haraway and Braidotti consider both the positive and the
negative effects of science’s capacity to undermine human exceptionality and to put the
human in one order with other species entail a range of phenomena .In the interview with
Haraway, Nicholas Gane (2006) observes that in “Manifesto for Cyborg” Haraway considers
technology as neither positive nor negative (p. 151.) On the one hand, she favors the fact that
science undoes human exceptionality by bringing the humans to close proximity with non-
humans (Haraway 2008, p. 12), on the other hand, she observes that science and technology,
and their unequal spread in the world, re-shapes social relations and create new inequalities
Braidotti (2002) also notice that the breaching of the boundaries between the human
and the animal by science entails different consequences. On the one hand, she writes about
the fact that bringing the human and the animal in close proximity entails the emergence of
new, post-humanist, non-unitary subject, that is, unlike the human, is not involved in
hierarchical relation with other non-human species (Braidotti 2002, p. 70). On the other hand,
Braidotti (2002) writes that medical science, especially such medical technologies, as
transplantation and artificial reproduction, entail commodification of certain humans (p. 222).
Braidotti (2002) observes that reproductive technologies construct the bodies of women for
whom surrogacy or gamete donations is a source of money, as “the site of the natural” (p.
233). Braidotti (2002) writes that “in this respect, the highly sophisticated discourse of high-
tech modernity leaves the female subject where it was before modernity, namely assimilated
to nature, identified with reproduction and inimical to civilized progress.” (p. 233).
It is necessary to mention that, unlike Agamben, in their theories, Braidotti and
Haraway, discuss concrete machines, such as computers, for instance, and concrete
technologies, such as artificial reproductive technologies or genetic engineering. In chapter 1
I have discussed Oliver's (2009) analysis of Agamben's theory, in which she claims that the
introduction of machines to our life can erase the opposition between the human and the
animal, uniting them together by the category of living and opposing the living to
mechanistic, represented by machines and technology. In this chapter I want to discuss how
in Braidotti's and Haraway's vision machines and technology influence the relations between
the animal and the human, and, perhaps, produce the division between the living and the
I argue that in Haraway's and Braidotti's theory machines and technology play a rather
ambiguous role. On the one hand, they have the potential of erasing the binary opposition of
the human and the animal and, speaking in Braidotti's parlance, “marrying zoe to bios” (p.
170); and the nomad or the cyborg that emerge when the boundaries between the human, the
animal and he machine are blurred has the potential to produce the politics without the
opposition of the dominant Self and the Other. On the other hand, if we take the case of
surrogate motherhood, when biomedical technologies intervene into woman's body, and the
border between the human and the machine is breached as the surrogate mother becomes akin
with the machine, a “human incubator for someone else's child” (Niekerk & Zyl 1995, p.
347), this case does not fit into the politics of erased divisions and oppositions. As those who
do surrogacy to gain financial profit and those who hire a surrogate to bear a baby for them
normally belong to different classes and sometimes even ethnicities (Kessler 2009, p. 169), I
claim that, surrogate mothers are reduced to non-human. On the one hand, they are reduced to
the animal, to what Agamben calls bare life, as it is reproduction, their nutritive, mere
biological functions that are put at stake when they engage in surrogacy as a kind of labor. On
the other hand they become machines, devices for bearing fetuses; but in their case, the
machine subjectivity, unlike Haraway's and Braidotti’s theories, does not produce the politics
In the first part of this chapter I will discuss how in Haraway's and Braidotti's vision
the cyborg and the nomad subjectivities can produce the politics of no opposition of the
dominant Self and the Other. In the second part of this chapter I will turn to the case of
surrogate mothers, whose bodily integrity is breached by biomedical technologies and they
become akin with machines (Niekerk & Zyl 1995, p. 348), however, unlike the nomad and
the cyborg, that are also intermediate forms between the human and the non-human (Styhre
2001, p. 5), the subjectivities of surrogate mothers do not produce the politics of no
hierarchies and oppositions; on the contrary, the existence of the offer in surrogate
motherhood and the demand in it is dependent on social inequalities (Kessler 2009, p. 169). 2.2 Cyborg and Nomad: Undoing Taxonomies
Haraway (2004) and Braidotti (2002) introduce the concepts of the cyborg and the
nomad accordingly to describe an unfixed, fluid and non-molar subjectivity which emerges
in-between the human and the non-human. (Styhre 2001, pp. 4-5). Both the nomad and the
cyborg are ontologies that produce certain kind of politics. Thereby, Haraway's (2004)
concept of the cyborg represents the confusion of the human, the animal and the machine.
She defines the cyborg as “a cybernetic organism, a hybrid of machine and organism, a
creature of social reality as well as a creature of fiction.” (Haraway 2004, p. 7) Haraway
(2004) writes that the cyborg is the ontology of our times (p. 8), and the politics that it gives
has no divisions on the subject and the object, on the Same and the Other.
Coming back to the previous chapter, I would like to highlight the fact that both in
Agamben's theory and in Haraway's and Braidotti's philosophy bare life, cyborg and nomad
are ontologies that produce politics. All these three ontologies emerge as a result of the
bringing into close proximity the human, the animal and the machine that is in its turn
achieved by the means of scientific inquiries in the realm of biology and medicine and by the
means of a range of biomedical technologies. However, bare life, cyborg and nomad,
according to Agamben (2002), Haraway (2004) and Braidotti (2002) produce significantly
In Agamben’s (2002) theory bare life is the human who is reduced to the animal, to
zoe, to mere biological life, and, hence, it is the human whose humanity and human rights are
suspended. Meanwhile, Haraway (2004) indicates that “cyborg signals … pleasurably tight
coupling” of the human and the animal (p. 10). She observes that the reduction of the distance
between the human and the animal is a fruitful ground for the emergence of new politics
(Haraway 2004, p. 11), because there is a “discursive tie between the colonized, the enslaved,
the noncitizen, and the animal – all reduced to type, all Others to rational man, and all
essential to his bright constitution – is at the heart of racism and flourishes lethally, in the
entails of humanism” (Haraway 2004, p. 18). Thereby, Haraway implies that the reduction of
the proximity between the human and the non-human is capable to entail the undoing of
boundaries that lie between the taxonomies and classes of humans and animals.
In Braidotti's (2002) theory the concept of the nomad is tightly connected with the
idea of 'becoming' that she borrows from A Thousand Plateaus of Giles Deleuze and Felix
Guattari. Thus, in her theory the transgression of the boundaries between the human, the
animal and the machine that leads to the emergence of the nomad is a form of becoming:
becoming the other, moving “into the direction of the others of classical dualism” (Braidotti
2002, p. 119). As Braidotti (2002) observes, becoming is a tool to deconstruct “the dominant
masculine, white, heterosexual subject-position” (p. 119). Thereby, Braidotti's nomad, that
becomes the machine and the animal, challenges the domination of that group of people that
has been considered dominant group since early modernity (such as white, male, middle-
class). Thereby, in Haraway’s and Braidotti's theory bringing the human to the close
proximity with the animal has the potential of producing the politics of no hierarchies and
oppositions, while in Agamben's theory, the erasure of the distance between the human and
the animal endangers the humanity and the rights of the human.
It is necessary to mention, that in Haraway’s (2004) theory cyborg emerges not only
as a result of the crossing of the borders between the human and the animal, – it also appears
as a result of the blurring of the boundaries between the living organism and the machine (p.
10). Haraway explains this boundary transcendence by the fact that modern machines, for
instance those that are created on the model of human intellect, “are lively, too”. (Gane 2006,
p. 141). She writes that the existence of machines that can imitate human thinking challenges
the dualities of “natural and artificial, mind and body, self-developing and externally
In this sense, Haraway’s idea about machines acquiring human intellect and
consciousness and, thus, being in some way also alive corresponds with Braidotti’s (2002)
observation of the fact that machines are human oriented in a sense that many of them imitate
human nervous system, human consciousness and human information perception (p. 222).
Thereby, Haraway’s cyborg and Braidotti's nomad emerge as the result of scientific
knowledge breaching in various ways the borders between the human, the animal and the
machine by the fact that they identify the similarities between the human and the non-human
and by technology’s intervention into human body, that influences human biological life
functions and, hence, make human body akin to the machine.
My analysis of the meaning that Haraway ad Braidotti ascribe to machine in their
philosophy drives me to the conclusion that in their theory machine is a facet of the Other.
According to Haraway and Braidotti, by science and technology breaches the borders of the
human and give the capacity to the human to become the machine, the Other. This becoming
implies the de-centralization of the human as the dominant Self of modernity and, hence,
entails the destruction of the oppositions and hierarchies.
In Agamben's philosophy technology and science also affect human's sense of
exception. However, in his theory the decentralization of the human entails the production of
the animalized man, whose rights and humanity are suspended. Agamben (2002) names the
process of the animalization of the human 'anthropological machine', and in this context
machine stands for the rational, artificial entity that dehumanizes the human and deprives him
of his mystery by reducing him to the animal (Oliver 2009, p. 235).
In Haraway’s and Braidotti’s theory, unlike Agamben's philosophy, machine does not
threat the humanity, on the contrary, while the machine, along with the animal, is the other of
the human, blurring of the borders between the human, the animal and the machine has the
potential of bringing a new social order of no dominant Self and the Other, of no hierarchy of
the human and non-human, of no opposition of zoe and bios.2.3 Artificial Reproduction: Becoming Machine or Becoming Animal?
Haraway (2004) writes that the breaching of the boundaries between the human, the
animal and the machine can exercise a positive influence: cyborg world, according to
Haraway (2004) is a place 'in which people are not afraid of their joint kinship with animals
and machines, not afraid of permanently partial identities and contradictory standpoints' (p.
13). Thus, cyborg ontology is capable of breaking hierarchies, dominant standpoints and
oppositions. However, Haraway (2004) mentions the reverse side that the cyborg world may
When discussing the negative sides of the world where the human, the animal and the
machine are mixing into one creature called cyborg, Haraway (2004) observes the possibility
of “final appropriation of women's bodies” (p. 28). She observes that “the situation of
women in a world is so intimately restructured through the social relations of science and
technology” (Haraway 2004, p. 25). Haraway (2004) does not elaborate on how exactly
women’s bodies can be appropriated, however, in the interview with Gane (2004) she says
that the fact that species interfere and are not taxonomically closed anymore is interconnected
with various kinds of body instrumentalization and the existence of bio-capital (p. 144).
Moreover, Gane (2006) notes that in Modest-Witness, Haraway argues that life is getting
commodified: according to Gane (2006), in Haraway's thought life “becomes a site of power
Following Foucault's idea of bio-power, Haraway (2006) introduces the concept of
'techno-power': it is a form a biopolitics that “has not gone away, but … has been reworked,
mutated, trans-ed, technologized and instumentalized differently.” (p. 148). In Haraway's
thought techno-power differs from biopower by the fact that the exercise of techno-power on
life is facilitated by bio- and medical technologies, and human life becomes a part of
biocapital and, hence, is commodified. In her interview with Gane and in A Manifesto forCyborg Haraway describes organ transplantation, genetic engineering and artificial
reproduction as the examples of techno-power being at work. Braidotti (2002) also observes
the fact that technologies become bio-technologies in a sense that technologies are getting
more body- and organic life- oriented (p. 215).
Following Haraway's logic, it is legitimate to say that bio- and medical technologies
intervene into human body and, thus, the inorganic blends with the organic, and the human
whose body is intervened by medical and bio-technology, can be considered a cyborg. In such
a case, surrogate mothers may be considered to be cyborgs as well, as their bodies are
intervened by a range of biomedical technologies, and whose identities are compared by
some scholars to those of machines (Niekerk & Zyl, 1995, p. 347). I agree that in the case of
surrogate mothers what we deal with is not fully human. However, the cyborg that emerges
due to the intervention of technologies to the human does not belong to Braidotti's and
Haraway's cyborg world of the lack of oppositions and hierarchies that I described in the
previous part of this chapter. On the contrary, I argue, that such a cyborg becomes inferior to
fully humans, to those, whose humanity was not altered by the contact with either animals or
In this section of Chapter 2 I want to discuss the paradox of surrogate motherhood that
implies the fact that although surrogate mothers can be considered cyborgs as the integrity of
their bodies is breached by technologies, however, they do not produce the politics of no
opposition of the dominant Self and the Other, of no hierarchies.
To support my point about surrogate motherhood producing inequalities in society, I
would like, firstly, to turn to the essay The Dialectics of Sex by Shulamith Firestone (1970).
In her essay, published about a decade earlier than Haraway's A Manifesto for Cyborg,
Firestone (1970) claims that the oppression of women should be explained not only by
different economic conditions of men and women, but also by the so-called fundamental,
biological difference (p. 6, p. 8). This difference, according to Firestone (1970), is embedded
in our reproductive systems (p. 11). Hence, she suggests that by the means of artificial
reproduction, that would erase the biological difference between the man and the woman, it
is possible to achieve equality in the society. Firestone (1970) calls the human to transcend
his/her biology by the means of technology (pp. 10 – 11), however, as I said in Chapter 1,
Agamben (2002) expresses anxiety about technologies taking the grip of human biological
life: in his theory this means the animalization of the human and reduction of the human to
I assume, that in the case of surrogacy Agamben's fear of technology's capacity to
strip the human of his/her humanity is rather appropriate. While Firestone (1970) writes that
the introduction of artificial reproduction would mean that human biology is not human
destiny any more, and, in her vision, that would produce equality among men and women,
however, Firestone's theory lacks the intersectional analysis. Perhaps, in 1970s she could not
predict the fact that the access to reproductive technologies would be uneven and this
asymmetry would be explained by race and class differences (Kessler 2009, p. 169). While
Firestone (1970) claims that reproductive technologies can bring equality between sexes, she
forgets about class and race division.
Documentary film Google Baby (2009) vividly performs how class and race
differences are embedded in the asymmetry of the access to reproductive technologies. The
film shows how low-class Indian women and working-class American woman act as
surrogates for middle-class Israeli couples. Thus, the film supports the argument about race
and class inequalities producing uneven access to reproductive technologies and even
The film provides with the insights on how surrogate mothers become commodified
and objectified. Thus, the bodies of surrogate Indian mothers are under surveillance of
doctors: their freedom for movement is restricted, as they have to stay in the ward, their day
schedule and diet are organized and designed by doctors.
The fact that in Google Baby (2009) surrogates come from India, a post-colonial
Eastern country, and that surrogates' freedom to move is restricted, in my opinion, resonates
with Achille Mbembe's (2008) description of slavery as a 'biopolitical experimentation' (p.
160). Firstly, Mbembe (2008) emphasizes the fact that slavery was race-based (p. 161).
Surrogacy can also be considered race-based: Google baby (2009) shows that it is women of
former colonies, of certain color that do surrogacy not to exceed the limits of their biology,
but to gain money for basic needs. Of course, it would be erroneous to claim that it is only
non-white women who act as surrogate mothers. However, the number of surrogate mothers
from the so-called third world is higher the number of women coming from developed
countries (Hervey, 1998). In this sense, by pointing at racial factor at women's acting as
surrogate mother, I mean not the skin color, but the belonging to the global East.
Secondly, Mbembe (2008) highlights the fact that “as an instrument of labor, the slave
has a price. As a property, he or she has a value.” (p. 160) The fact that the slave could be
bought echoes with the fact that surrogates can actually be bought as well: Google Baby
(2009) performs that the younger the surrogate is and the better her health is, the more she
Thirdly, Mbembe (2008) emphasizes the fact that “slave's life is possessed by the
master” (p. 161) which implies that slaves life structure and freedom of movement depends
on the decision of his master. In the same way surrogate's life is for 9 months dependent in
Moreover, Mbembe (2008) writes that the slave is treated “as a mere tool and
instrument of production” (p. 161). Meanwhile, surrogate mothers are treated as tools of
reproduction. Nieker & Zyl (1995) point out that surrogates serve as incubators for fetuses (p.
347). Following Mbembe (2008) who compares slaves to instruments of production and
claiming that surrogate mothers are instruments of reproduction, I cannot but refer to Chasin's
(1995) observation of such machines as labor-saving devices and ATMs having identities
similar to servants and slaves (p. 81). Thus, according to Chasin (1995), before the advent of
labor saving devices the household work in the US was performed by people of color and
immigrants (Chasin 1995, p. 81). According to Chasin (1995), the relations between hired
housekeepers and their employers and the relations between labor-saving devices and their
owners are similar in the sense that they are built on the model of subject-object relations (p.
The comparison between surrogates, slaves and machines (such as labor saving device
or incubators) is useful for me to support the following claim: surrogate mothers, that, as I
explained in the beginning of this chapter, can be considered what Haraway (2004; 2008) and
Braidotti (2002) call cyborg or nomad, cannot produce the politics of no oppositions and
divisions, as their labor is embedded in class and racial inequality. Besides, they are
obviously dehumanized by the fact that what is at stake is their mere nutritive functions, and,
hence, they are reduced to machines or to bare life .
If in Mbembe's (2008) analysis slavery is an example of biopolitics at work, then
surrogacy can also be considered as an instance of biopolitics. While, from Mbembe's
perspective plantation is a biopolitical space (p. 161) and the slaves are in Agamben’s
parlance bare life, humans whose humanity is suspended, then in the case of surrogacy, the
ward becomes a biopolitical space and surrogate mothers become bare life.
Thus, I assume that if we can consider surrogate mothers to be bare life, then it is
legitimate to claim that their turning into bare life is a result of the work of anthropological
machine that I discussed in Chapter 1. Since in Agamben's theory bare life is produced due
the erasure of the distance between the human and the animal and the target of human
biology by technologies, surrogate mothers can be considered as the product of the work of
the anthropological machine, because by the means of reproduction technologies their
existence and labor is reduced to nutritive functions that humans share with animals. As I
have mentioned in the introduction to this chapter, medical and bio-technologies, according
to Braidotti (2002) construct the bodies of women who do surrogacy or donate their gametes
as “the site of the natural” (p. 233). In other words, in the case of artificial reproduction,
technology targets pure human biology, and, moreover, commodifies it. Thus, the grip on
human biological life that medical and bio-technology get corresponds to a great extent with
Agamben's anxious vision of technology managing human biological life. Agamben fears that
along with managing biological life, technology also reduces the human to the animal. In the
case of artificial reproduction, medical technologies bring up nutritive functions of human
life, those functions that the human shares with the animal and, thus, reduces the human to
Meanwhile, I assume, that surrogate mothers can still be considered what Haraway
and Braidotti call nomads or cyborgs, as their molar, steady identity is challenged by the
intervention of technologies in their bodies. Thereby, my idea of surrogate mothers being
human with suspended humanity, bare life, the production of anthropological machine,
challenges Haraway's and Braidotti's claim of cyborg and nomad being ontologies that
produce the politics of no division of dominant Self and the Other. Surrogate mothers, as I
have examined, serve as labor saving devices for other people, which entails the hierarchical
relations between people-labor-saving devices and those who use their labor.
Although in this chapter I contested Haraway's cyborg and Braidotti's nomad as
ontologies that give the politics of no oppositions. I refrain from labeling Haraway's and
Braidotti's theory as irrelevant or utopist. In my opinion, it is necessary to mention that in
Haraway's and Braidotti's theory the category the category of the human is used in the
meaning of masculine, white domination, as opposed to animal and machine, that represent
the Others of that white masculine domination. Thus, Styhre (2001) writes that “for Braidotti
the notion of the nomad subject is employed to escape the hegemonic and exclusionary views
of subjectivity offered by phallocentric thinking.” (p. 4). However, in Agamben's theory the
category of the human is not gender-colored and that is, perhaps, the reason why the feminist
thinkers and Agamben consider the breaching of the boundaries between the human, the
machine and the animal in such a different way. 2. 4 Conclusion
In this chapter I have discussed the role that machines play in Haraway’s and
Braidotti’s theory. Haraway (2004; 2008) and Braidotti (2002) introduce the ontology of
cyborg and nomad, accordingly. These ontologies imply the blurring of the boundaries
between the human, the animal and the machine. The ontology of cyborg and nomad produce,
according to Haraway and Braidotti, a certain kind of politics. Thus, both Haraway (2004;
2008) and Braidotti (2002) write that the breaching of the boundaries between species and the
undoing of fixed, molar taxonomies entails the undoing of hierarchies and oppositions
between the dominant Self and the Other. However, turning to the case of surrogacy, a
procedure in which technology intervenes into human body, and, hence, surrogate mothers
can be considered as cyborgs or nomads, I claim that surrogate mothers do not produce the
politics of no oppositions and divisions that Haraway (2004; 2008) and Braidotti (2002) write
about. Using Mbembe's (2008) theory to draw a comparison between the surrogate mother,
the slave and the machine, I claim that since surrogate mothers' labor is reduced by
biomedical technologies to the functions of mere biological life and since the essence of the
work of Agamben's (2002) anthropological machine is the reduction of the human to animal
by the means of technology, surrogate mothers can be regarded as bare life, the production of
the work of anthropological machine. Chapter 3 Fukuyama: Redeeming the Human 3.1 Introduction
In chapter 2 I discussed how differently Agamben and Haraway and Braidotti consider
the transcendence of the borders of the human, the animal and the machine. While in
Agamben's (2002) theory what emerges when the boundaries of the human and the animal are
breached is bare life, the human with suspended humanity, in Haraway's and Braidotti's
philosophy it is the cyborg and the nomad, ontologies that produce the politics of no division
on the dominant Self and the Other. Thus, Agamben (2002) regards science and technology's
capacity to breach the boundaries of the human as dangerous, while Haraway (2004) and
Braidotti (2002) claim that nomad and cyborg subjectivities can produce a new kind of
politics of no hierarchies. In both philosophies the reduction of the distance between the
human and the human is done by the means of sciences and the technologies that these
In his book Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology Revolution
contemporary political scientist Francis Fukuyama (2002) expresses the anxiety about the
breaching of the boundaries between the human and the non-human that is quite similar to the
one that Agamben (2002) expresses in The Open: Man and Animal. Fukuyama (2002)
discusses how the breaching of the boundaries between the human and the animal, puts
human animality, human biology at stake of economic, trade and social relations, and, hence,
contributes to the creation of a biopolitical state (p. 155). Through his empirical research
Fukuyama (2002) shows how in biopolitical state, where human health is a big value and a
commodity at the same time, the access to health service and biomedical technologies is not
equal due to class differences (p. 175). Thus, Fukuyama (2002) manages to observe what
Haraway (2004) and Braidotti (2002) seem to omit in their analysis: biomedical technologies
are not equally distributed. Given that, Fukuyama (2002) suggests that the uniqueness and
exceptionality of the human should not be contested (p. 171), and biomedical technologies
should stop revealing and targeting human biological functions and creating a market of
services that are aimed at altering human biology (pp. 182- 183).
The argument of this chapter is that, although in his analysis Fukuyama (2002) ,
unlike Haraway (2004) and Braidotti (2002), embraces the fact of the unequal access to
biomedical technologies, his theory, nonetheless, has a significant drawback: while he calls
for setting strict boundaries of the human and not allowing technologies and sciences to blur
those boundaries, his idea of taking the meaning of the human for granted can turn into the
dehumanization of the human. In other words, Fukuyama's (2002) call to stop the erasure of
the boundaries that lie between the human and the non-human, that seems to echo with
Agamben's (2002) call to stop the work of anthropological machine that animalizes the
human, can actually turn into nothing else but the work of anthropological machine, as taking
for granted the notion of the human, can push certain groups of people outside of the borders
To support my argument I will, firstly, discuss Fukuyama’s (2002) concept of human
dignity that, as he claims, every human being possesses, and will explore whether Agamben
(2002) uses any similar notion of what Fukuyama (2002) names human dignity. Secondly, I
will discuss how Fukuyama engages with the question of the role of natural and medical
sciences and modern technologies, especially biomedical technologies in the blurring of the
boundaries between the human and the animal. Thirdly, I will explore what sort of politics in
Fukuyama’s opinion the breaching of the borders between the human and the non-human
may produce. I will compare his vision with that of Agamben, Haraway and Braidotti. 3.2 Human as an Uncontestable Category
Fukuyama (2002) writes that the fact that the modern science and technology identify
within the non-humans the features that has always been considered only exclusively inherent
in the humans threatens human dignity. In Fukuyama’s (2002) thought human dignity is
equal to the possession of “Factor X” (p. 171). By “Factor X” Fukuyama (2002) understands
the possession of all such qualities as “moral choice, or reason, or language, or sociability, or
sentience, or emotions, or consciousness, or any other quality that has been put forth as a
ground for human dignity” (p. 171).
This definition of what is Factor X that constitutes human dignity is rather imprecise.
However, I assume that Fukuyama (2002) gives such an imprecise definition of Factor X on
purpose. In Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology Revolution
Fukuyama (2002) traces how natural and medical sciences have been depriving the human
from the features that used to be human-specific only. Thus, he writes that the findings in the
field of ethology and primotology challenge the idea of culture and capacity for politics being
only human-specific characteristics (Fukuyama 2002, p. 145); and the promises of computer
scientists to create artificial intellect that would possess human consciousness calls in
question whether consciousness is a human defining feature (Fukuyama 2002, p. 170). Since
scientific inquiry perpetually challenges the idea of which characteristics are typical only for
human beings, Fukuyama (2002) tends not give a concrete range of characteristics that define
Fukuyama’s (2002) analysis of how various fields of science constantly undermine the
unique status of specificity of this or that formally human-specific feature echoes with
Agamben’s (2002) idea of perpetual work of anthropological machine which constantly
updates the meanings of the human and the non-human by moving the border line separating
the human from the non-human (p. 16). In Chapter 1, I have discussed the fact that natural
and medical sciences contribute immensely to the work of anthropological machine. From
my point of view, Fukuyama’s (2002) idea about sciences constantly updating our view of
what is human –specific and what is not is parallel to Agamben’s (2002) idea of
anthropological machine that perpetually produces new meanings of the human.
As the meaning of the human is challenged by the inquiries in the fields of natural,
medical and computer sciences, Fukuyama (2002) refrains from giving a very concrete
definition of the human, as it can be contested by any other finding in the realm of natural or
Fukuyama’s (2002) rather abstract definition of Factor X, in my opinion, echoes with
the conclusion that Agamben (2002) makes from Edward Tyson’s work treatise Orang-Outang, sive Homo Sylvestris: or, the Anatomy of a Pygmie: “man has no specific identity
other than the ability to recognize himself (p. 26). I assume, that both Agamben (2002) and
Fukuyama (2002) try to say that since various findings in different branches of science
constantly challenge the notion of the human, the meaning of the human will always be
Since Fukuyama’s (2002) theory is rather policy oriented in the sense that he suggests
on how biomedical technologies should be regulated and what meaning the human should
have in the times of flourishing biomedical technologies, he actually suggests that the
humanity of the human should not be questioned at all. Fukuyama (2002) writes that every
human a priori possesses the so-called Factor X: “every member of the human species
possesses a genetic endowment that allows him or her to become a whole human being, an
endowment that distinguishes a human essence from other types of creatures” (p. 171).
Fukuyama’s (2002) idea about human uniqueness despite any scientific evidence
about the lack of human exceptionality, in my opinion, sounds quite similar to the theological
idea of human uniqueness in this world. Fukuyama (2002) does not make direct references to
any theological doctrines, however, in my interpretation of his work, he implicitly relies on
Christianity, and this also makes his theory resonate with that of Agamben. In chapter 1
discussed how Agamben calls for religious immunization of the category of the human
against scientific claims about human not having any significant difference from the animal.
Firstly, Fukuyama (2002) calls for theology, philosophy and politics to control the
operation of biomedical technologies and the role of sciences in our life (p. 185). He writes
that “it is only 'theology, philosophy, or politics' that can establish the ends of science and the
technology that science produces, and pronounce on whether these ends are good or bad” (p.
185). Thus, Fukuyama (2002) actually claims that it is non-materialistic sciences, the
sciences on the non-biological side of the human that should control the work of the
materialistic sciences that are engaged with the research on human biology.
A similar sentiment Oliver (2009) observes in Agamben’s The Open: Man andAnimal. Oliver (2009) writes that “Agamben diagnoses one of the central problems with
scientific discourse as the tendency to reduce life to bare life by emptying it of all mystery
and therefore its meaning. Without mystery, life is more like a functioning machine than an
assembly of living creatures.” (p. 240). This quote brings me back to Chapter 1 of this work,
where I discussed that one of the meanings of Agamben’s concept of the machine is the
deprivation of the human of its celestial and lofty meaning, and the reduction of human
existence to the mechanistic functions of nutritive life, such as reproduction, growth,
Secondly, Fukuyama’s (2002) incline to appeal to religion as to the tool that can
constrain the animalization of the human done by biomedicine, is reflected in his analysis of
how various countries address the problems related to biomedicine. Fukuyama (2002) writes
that many Asian countries “have not been nearly as concerned with the ethical dimension of
biotechnology” as European countries (p. 192) Fukuyama (2002) explains this by the fact that
Asian countries do not profess Christianity; he writes that “Taoism and Shinto are animalistic
and invest both animals and inanimate objects with spiritual qualities” (p. 192), and
“Buddhism conflates human and natural creation into a single seamless cosmos” (p. 192).
Thereby, Fukuyama (2002) concludes that there is an interconnection between religions that
do not draw a distinct line between the human and the animal and the lack of concern from
the side of the society that professes those religions about the operation of biomedical
technologies which, in Fukuyama’s view, are capable to deprive the human from his dignity
by reducing him to the animal (p. 192).
Thus, Fukuyama’s (2002) idea of the human dignity that is hard to define but that
exists in every human being a priori, is inflated with religious idea of the mystery of the
human being. In Fukuyama’s (2002) vision human dignity is endangered by natural and
medical sciences and the technologies they produce. Fukuyama’s (2002) anxious sentiment
about human being demystified by biomedicine resembles of Agamben’s idea about science
fueling the work of the anthropological machine and reducing the human to the mechanic
3.3 Science and technology: erasing human complexity
Fukuyama (2002) engages with the discussion of the role of natural and medical
sciences in the erasure of the distinctions between the human and the non-human in a way
analogous to Agamben. While Agamben (2002) describes how the work of Edward Tyson on
comparative anatomy of the ape and the human (p. 25) and Marie-Francois-Xavier Bichat's
division of human life's functions on relational and nutritive (p. 14) contributed to the thought
that the animal can be situated within the human, Fukuyama (2002) also observes that natural
and medical sciences have reduced the gap between the human and the animal. Thus, he
observes that Darwin's evolutionary theory challenged human’s exceptionality by suggesting
that humans and animals share a significant number of features: with Darwin's evolutionary
theory “many of the attributes that were once held to be unique to human beings, including
language, culture, reason, consciousness, and the like – are now seen as characteristics of
wide variety of non-human animals” (Fukuyama 2002, p. 144). Fukuyama also (2002) refers
to the work of contemporary primatologist and ethologist Frans de Waal and his findings
about chimpanzees that just like humans, can transmit culture from one generation to the
other (p. 145). The conclusion that Fukuyama (2002) makes after analyzing how natural and
medical sciences influence the shaping of the categories of the human and the animal is quite
similar to that of Agamben (2002). Fukuyama (2002) writes that natural and medical sciences
bring to the close proximity the animal and the human, and, hence, deprive the human from
his exceptionality in natural world, by reducing him to the animals.
Fukuyama (2002) is preoccupied not only with the role that medical and natural
sciences play in reducing the gap between the human and the non-human. Unlike Agamben
(2002), Fukuyama (2002) engages with the question of the blurring of the boundaries
between the human and the machine. He writes that while human consciousness used to be
perceived as a human-specific feature that distinguishes humans from non-humans, there are
computer and artificial intelligence scientists who are convinced that with more powerful
computers and new approaches to computing, such as neural networks, we are on the verge of
a breakthrough in which mechanical computers will achieve consciousness” (p. 166).
Like Haraway (2008) and Braidotti (2002), Fukuyama (2002) is interested in the
breaching of the boundaries not only between the human and the animal, but also between the
human and the machine. In Chapter 2 I discussed the fact that in Haraway’s (2004) theory
technology is ubiquitous and it intervenes into human bodies (p. 12). Fukuyama (2002) is
also interested in the fact how technologies intervene into human body. Fukuyama (2002)
observes that neuropharmacology intervenes into human consciousness to regulate our
emotions (p. 172). To do that, according to Fukuyama (2002), neuropharmacologies divide
complex human emotions on good and bad (p. 172). Such a mechanistic division of complex
human feelings and emotional experiences on simply positive and negative, according to
Fukuyama (2002), threatens human dignity, as it endangers the complexity of human nature.
In the previous part of this chapter I have mentioned that Fukuyama’s anxiety about natural
and medical sciences reducing the human to basic biological functions echoes with the
meaning of Agamben’s (2002) anthropological machine that deprives the human of his
mystery and celestial side and reduces to mere biology. Fukuyama’s (2002) idea about
neuropharmacology that reduces the complexity of human feelings and emotions, I think, also
fits into the essence of the image of the anthropological machine. Since, as Fukuyama (2002)
claims, human emotions are an example of how human nature is unfathomable (p. 172),
neuropharmacology applies such technologies that aim to disrupt the complexity of human
nature and to mechanistically divide human emotions on good and bad.
However, when Haraway (2004; 2008) and Braidotti (2002) discuss the intervention
of technologies into human, they discuss physical intervention entailed by such technologies
as artificial reproduction or genetic engineering. The case of drugs that regulate human
emotional condition described by Fukuyama (2002, p. 172-173), of course does not entail
physical intervention into human body. However, both neuropharmacological drugs like
Ritalin and Prozac and artificial reproduction are “technologies of life” (Rose 2007, p.17) .
Nicolas Rose (2007) writes that “technologies of life” are more than just equipment
and techniques, such as brain imaging, or genetic testing, or surgical technologies to perform
various kinds of transplantations (p. 17). In Rose’s (2007) opinion, technology is an
‘assemblage of social and human relations within which equipment and techniques are only
one element” (p. 17). In Roses’s (2007) understanding “technologies …are hybrid
assemblages of knowledge, instruments, persons, systems of judgment, buildings, and spaces,
underpinned at the programmatic level by certain presuppositions and assumptions about
human beings” (p. 17). In chapter 1 I argued that Rose’s (2007) definition of technology is
applicable to describe what Agamben means by anthropological machine. The fact that
Rose’s (2007) definition is applicable to both Fukuyama’s (2002) understanding of
technology and the meaning of Agamben’s anthropological machine supports my idea about
Fukuyama’s theory being an example of the operation of anthropological machine, as what
Fukuyama (2002) writes about is nothing but the situation of the animal within the human by
natural and medical sciences and the management of that animality or human biological life
by the means of biomedical technology.
Thus, Rose (2007) writes that “technologies of life” seek “to refigure …vital
processes themselves in order maximize their functioning and enhance their outcomes.”
(p.17). Thus, just like artificial reproduction allows to choose a genetic parent for a child,
and, hence, to enhance the genetics of the artificially conceived child, such drugs as Ritalin
and Prozac, allow to muffle the so-called ‘bad’ human emotions that prevent people from
Rose’s (2007) idea about technologies’ of life capacity to maximize the functions of
human biological life resembles Haraway’s (2004) observation about the interconnection
between bio-capital and instrumentalization and commodification of human life (p. 144).
Meanwhile, the fact that in bio-capital, the society where human biological life becomes part
of the economy echoes with Agamben’s (2002) idea of technological control over human
biological life as the consequence of the animalization of the human being (pp. 82-83). 3. 4 Technology and Inequality
Fukuyama (2002) claims that natural and medical sciences and the technologies they
produce deprive the human of his uniqueness in contrast to other species. Unlike Haraway
(2004; 2008) and Braidotti (2002), Fukuyama (2002) claims that the blurring of the
boundary between the human and the animal will produce even more inequalities and
hierarchies than the strict distinction between the human and the animal (p. 153).
Fukuyama (2002) writes that in the society where the human and the animal are
brought to close proximity to each other, human biological life becomes at stake in the life of
such a society. Fukuyama (2002) follows Nietzsche to identify the negative “consequences of
modern natural science and the abandonment of the concept of human dignity” (p. 155): he
writes that the animalization of the human will lead to the society in which human health
becomes of primary importance (p. 155). According to Fukuyama (2002), the fact that society
assigns a great importance to human health entails the problem of unequal access to health
services and to biotechnologies that are proliferating nowadays (p. 155).
When Fukuyama (2002), following Nietzsche, mentions the society in which the
human is animalized and human health becomes one of the most important objectives of the
state, he implies nothing but the biopolitical state. Rose (2007) writes the in biopolitical state
biotech and pharmaceutical companies become active and important participants in state
economy, while human biological life becomes a commodity “that can be isolated, delimited,
stored, accumulated, mobilized, and exchanged, accorded a discrete value, traded across time,
space, species, contexts, enterprises” (p. 7).
In the previous part of this chapter I discussed that such a utilitarian attitude to human
biological life is a vivid example of the side-effect of the operation of Agamben’s
anthropological machine, when human’s so-called animality, or biological life, is targeted and
managed by the means of technology. As I explored earlier in this chapter, Fukuyama (2002)
writes that the way how biomedicine positions the human as an animal threatens human
dignity (p. 159), however, he is also concerned by the fact that in biocapital society, where
human biological life is what is at stake, the access to health services and medical
Rose (2007) writes that in the society where human health becomes a part of state
economy, the concern of medicine goes far beyond such tasks as ‘curing organic damage or
disease” (p. 17) According to Rose (2007), in a biopolitical state the tasks of medicine and
biomedicine engage the improvement of citizens’ health, the enhancement of their physical or
health abilities, in prevention of the diseases they are susceptible to (p.26). In other words, in
a biopolitical state, biomedicine offers a range of services that are not exclusively targeted at
health problems, some of them are aimed at improving the quality of individuals’ lives.
However, as Fukuyama (2002) observes, the medical services with which the biocapital
flourishes with are not accessible to everyone (p. 186).
When discussing the asymmetrical access to biomedical services, Fukuyama (2002) is
interested in how in the future when genetic enhancement will come of age great inequalities
among humans will emerge and will endanger the human dignity of those who do not have
access to genetic enhancement (p. 157).
In Fukuyama’s (2002) philosophy the scenario when technology gets a grip of the
human biological life, and human biological life becomes at stake of political and economic
relations is possible only in the future. However, coming back to my discussion of the theory
of Haraway (2008) and Braidotti (2002) in Chapter 2 of my thesis, I want to add that with the
spread of reproductive technologies human life, human nutritive functions are already
commodified, and the access to reproductive technologies is not even. I explored in Chapter
2, how those women who earn money by the means of acting as surrogate mothers, on the
one hand, acquire an identity of the animal, since it is only the nutritive functions of their life
that are engaged in this kind of labor. And, on the other hand, they acquire an identity of a
machine, since they are not emotionally attached to the babies they bear and simply serve as
incubators for embryos to mature. Thereby, in his futuristic forecasts of the inequalities that
biomedicine can create among the humans, Fukuyama (2002) fails to see that these
inequalities already exist, and they emerged due the asymmetrical access to reproductive
Therefore, Fukuyama’s (2002) claim about the necessity to draw a red line that would
separate the human from other species and would not allow the breaching of the boundary
between the human and the animal, and the human and the machine is, most probably,
outdated, as cyborg and nomadic subjectivities described in the theories of Haraway (2004;
2008) and Braidotti (2002) already exist. And while Fukuyama (2002) writes that it is
necessary to preserve the animal as the other for the sake of preserving human’s humanity,
the blurring of the borders between the human and the other (the animal and the machine) is
Thereby, Fukuyama's (2002) idea of setting concrete boundaries of the human
contradicts to the fact that these boundaries are already being transcended by such
technologies as artificial reproduction, for instance. Coming back to Chapter 2, where I
discussed surrogate mothers as cyborgs or nomads, whose identities are non-molar and not
fixed, I claim that Fukuyama's call for establishing “bright red line” (p. 159) of the border of
the human can be dangerous, because Fukuyama considers how in the future human's
subjectivity will be influenced by biomedical technology. However, if we take surrogate
mothers their subjectivities are already influenced by reproductive technology. When
Fukuyama (2002) writes that human emotions constitute the major element of Factor X that
distinguishes the human from other species (p. 170), surrogate mothers, for instance, may be
pushed out of the category of the human based on the fact that normally they do not have an
emotional attachment to expected baby (Niekerk & Zyl 1995, p. 348). As I claimed in the
previous chapter, the subjectivities of surrogate mothers resonate with those of machines or
animals. Hence, it is impossible to set a fixed border of the human, when this border is
The idea of the precariousness of such a line sounds even more convincing if we turn
back to the theory of Agamben (2002) in which he analyses how a range of discourses may
construct the human as non-human, and how the category of the human is ceaselessly
updated. Provided that the category of the human is changeable and unstable, I find
Fukuyama's (2002) call for setting the distinct boundaries of the human to be unrealistic, if
3. 5 Conclusion
In this chapter I discussed how Fukuyama's (2002) analysis of natural and medical
sciences and biotechnology's capacity to deprive the human of his sense of exceptionality is
quite similar to Agamben’s (2002) concept of anthropological machine that animalizes the
human and whose side-effect is technological management of human biological life.
However, Fukuyama's (2002) call for the creation of fixed boundaries of the human and
“allowing the state to make sure that no one falls outside it” does not mean the stoppage of
the anthropological machine and the dehumanization of the human. Since, for instance, the
subjectivities of surrogate mothers can be considered as emerging in-between the human, the
animal and the machine, the setting of fixed borders of the human, can lead to the
dehumanization of surrogates and their turning into bare life, the human with suspended
Conclusion
In this work I used Agamben's concept of anthropological machine to examine the
role of technology in biopolitical state. In chapter 1 I concluded that this concept
encompasses a range of meanings. Thus, anthropological machine stands for medical and
scientific knowledge about the human, medical and biomedical technologies that target
human biological life and the attitude to human biological life as to something close to the
animal, and, hence, something inferior to the so-called relational life and something that can
Engaging with the works of feminist thinkers Rosi Braidotti and Donna Haraway in
chapter 1, I concluded that in their work the concept of the machine is used as a species with
whom, just like with animals, humans are in constant interaction. In Braidotti's and
Haraway's theory the distance between the human, the animal and the machine is reduced by
a range of sciences and technologies, such as genetic engineering, reproductive technologies
and cybernetics. While in Chapter 1 I observe that Agamben sees the breeching of the
boundary between the human and the animal as a threat to the human, In chapter 2 engaging
with the theories of Braidotti and Haraway, I discuss their claim about the fact that the
erasure of the borders between the human, the animal and the machine offers a potential for
the creation of a new type of politics, which would be deprived of the existence of
oppositions, hierarchies and dominant Self. While in Agamben's philosophy the
transcendence of the border between the human and the animal leads to the emergence of
bare life – the human with suspended humanity and suspended human rights, in the theories
of Braidotti (2002) and Haraway (2004) the transcendence of the borders between the
species entails the emergence of the cyborg or the nomad, the ontological subjectivities that
produce the world order without taxonomies and hierarchies.
However, I challenge Haraway's (2004) and Braidotti's (2002) vision about the kind
of politics that the cyborg and the nomad can produce by discussing the asymmetric access to
reproductive technologies that exists in the world, and how women for whom surrogacy
becomes a form of labor gain the subjectivities of machines or animals.
While Braidotti (2002) and Haraway (2004; 2008) do not include the uneven access to
reproductive technologies in their analysis, Francis Fukuyama (2002), to whose theory I turn
in Chapter 3, offers an empirical research on how the access to biomedical technologies is not
equal. In his theory the animalization of the human is interdependent with the existence of
biocapital in which human health or, in Agamben's parlance, human biological life becomes a
commodity and is engaged in economic, trade and social relations. That said, Fukuyama
(2002) claims that in the society where human biology is at stake and where medical services
and biomedical technologies are not evenly accessible, there is a risk of posing a threat to the
human dignity of those who do not have the full access to medical services and biomedical
technologies of biocapital. Thereby, Fukuyama calls for the necessity to foster the borders of
the human by not allowing medical sciences and biomedical technologies to target human
biology and to reduce the human to mere nutritive functions.
It must be pointed out that in my work I refrained from considering Fukuyama's
(2002) political theory as a more adequate than the one of Haraway (2004) and Braidotti
(2002). I emphasized the fact that Fukuyama's (2002) call for the drawing of the red line
around humanity is rather problematic, since the example of surrogate mothers shows that
some people, due to the intervention of biomedical technologies, already have unfixed,
unstable identities, and the setting of certain borders/factors that would fence about the
human, may lead to the risk of the dehumanization of people whose subjectivities have been
destabilized by biomedical technologies.
My analysis of theories of Agamben, Braidotti, Haraway and Fukuyama makes me
conclude that Agamben's concept of anthropological machine is a powerful and succinct
metaphor for the description of a significant role that science and technology play in a
biopolitical state. Thus, by targeting human biological life and having the capacity to manage
it, they have the potential to refigure the meaning of the human and to move the borders of
In my research I leave open the question about which of the two types of politics, the
one that seeks to redeem the human or the one that aims at decentralizing the human is more
humane. My thesis discusses that the politics of the redeeming of the human suggested by
Fukuyama (2002) has the potentiality of turning certain groups of people into bare life.
Agamben’s (2002) notion of anthropological machine demonstrates how setting of the
boundaries of the human for the sake of saving human’s humanity can turn into the
production of bare life, the human that is stripped of his/her human rights. Meanwhile, the
politics of unfixed subjectivities, of uncertain boundaries of the human and the non-human
suggested by Braidotti (2002) and Haraway (2004; 2008) can also lead to the maintenance of
hierarchical social relations. Thus, the problem of what type of politics has the potential to
annihilate the opposition of the dominant Self and the Other remains the subject open for
References
Agamben, G. (1998) Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford: StanfordUniversity Press.
Agamben, G. (2002). The open: man and animal. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Braidotti, R. (2002). Metamorphoses: towards a materialist theory of becoming. Cambridge:Polity
Campbell, T. (2008). Translator's note: bios, immunity, life. The thought of Roberto Esposito. In R. Esposito, Biopolitics and philosophy (pp. vii – xli).Minneapolis: University ofMinnesota Press.
Chasin, A. (1995). Class and its close relations: identities among women, servants andmachines. In J. Halberstam & I. Livingston (Eds.), Posthuman Bodies (pp. 73-97. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Foucault, M. (2003). Society must be defended: lectures at the college de France, 1975 –1976. New York: Picador.
Firestone, S. (1970). The Dialectic of sex: the case for feminist revolution. New York: Farrar,Straus and Giroux.
Frank, B. Z. (Producer & Director). (2009). Google Baby. [Film]. Israel: Brandcomproductions.
Fukuyama, F. (2002). Our posthuman future: consequences of the biotechnology revolution. New York: Farrar Straus & Giroux.
Gane, N. (2006). We have never been human, what is to be done? Interview with DonnaHaraway. Theory, Culture, Society, 23 (7-8), 135-158. doi: 10.1177/0263276406069228
Haraway, D. J. (2004). A manifesto for cyborg: science, technology, and socialist feminism inthe 1980s. In D. J. Haraway, The Haraway reader (pp. 7-42). New York: Routledge.
Haraway, D. J. (2008). When species meet. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Hervey, T. K. (1998). Buy baby: the European Union and regulation of human reproduction. Oxford hourna of legal studies, 18(2), 207 – 233.
März 22 - 25, Stattkino am Löwenplatz 11, Luzern Einführung in den Filmabend vom 22.03.2012 - Classic Night Heute Abend haben wir für Sie zwei Perlen des Genres herausgesucht, die mit Fug und Recht als Klassi-ker des zeitgenössischen Tanzfilmes bezeichnet werden dürfen: Denn sie ebneten den Weg des zeitge-nössischen Tanzes ins Kino. Die britische Produktion Dead Dreams of Mono
Regulating NeedDeciding on public financial intervention withinthe fields of healthcare and development aidAnna Krohwinkel-Karlsson and Ebba SjögrenRegulating NeedDeciding on public financial intervention withinthe fields of healthcare and development aidAnna Krohwinkel-Karlsson and Ebba SjögrenScore working paper 2006:1ISBN 91-89658-38-8ISSN 1404-5052 Deciding on public financial intervent