Microsoft word - schuster's review of marinoff edited and corrected by scs.–
Marinoff’s Therapy: A Critique of His Books on Philosophical Practice Shlomit C. Schuster Shlomit C. Schuster is a practicing philosophical counselor. She has written several scholarly articles on philosophical counseling and is the author of Philosophy Practice: An Alternative to Counseling and Psychotherapy (Praeger, 1999) and The Philosopher’s Autobiography: A Qualitative Study (Praeger, 2003). Her home in cyberspace is www.geocities.com/centersophon Lou Marinoff, Therapy for the Sane: How Philosophy Can Change Your Life (also published as The Big Questions: How Philosophy Can Change Your Life), New York, Bloomsbury, 2003, pp. 400, $24.95. ISBN 1582342539 Lou Marinoff, Philosophical Practice, New York, Academic Press, 2002, pp. 411, $69.95. ISBN 0124715559 Lou Marinoff, Plato, Not Prozac; Applying Eternal Wisdom to Everyday Problems (also published as Plato, Not Prozac; Applying Philosophy to Everyday Problems),New York, HarperCollins, 1999, pp. 308, $13.00. ISBN 0060931361
Lou Marinoff, author of the bestseller Plato, Not Prozac, and a professor of philosophy at
the City College of New York is not only a controversial figure at his university, but also among
his philosophical counseling colleagues; some of the latter even consider him dangerous. This is
because he has attempted to present himself as the international leader and legislator of this new
type of counseling. My aim in this review essay is to expose and challenge some basic problems
In 1999, when Marinoff, presented his first book on philosophical counseling, Plato, not Prozac, its aim was to reach the masses. At his publisher’s request Marinoff created the acronym
“PEACE” for the five stages of the process that his clients go through: “Problem identification,”
“Expressing emotion,” “Analyzing options,” “Contemplation,” “Equilibrium.” Yet, in Philosophical Practice (p. 167), Marinoff discloses that when he worked with his clients in the
period preceding the publication of Plato, not Prozac, he “eschewed the very notion of a method
as antithetical to philosophical inquiry into personal problems.” He further mentions that when
he reflected on his practice for the purpose of differentiating it from what psychologists and
psychiatrist do, he discovered that he actually had worked methodologically with the approach
he later named the PEACE process. Then Marinoff claims, in a rather paradoxical manner, that
PEACE is “a contentless form that suggests some contours of philosophical counseling, without
prescribing any particular methodology” (Philosophical Practice, p. 167). Nevertheless, he still
calls it a meta-methodology that can be applied for working with organizations, as well with
individuals. (Philosophical Practice, p. 168).
Like many other philosophical counselors, Marinoff found his inspiration for his
counseling practice mainly in the pioneering work of Gerd B. Achenbach. In 1981, Achenbach, a
German philosopher, opened the first philosophical counseling practice in the world. He is
briefly mentioned a few times in Plato, not Prozac, Philosophical Practice, and Therapy for the Sane. Except for applying the term “philosophical counseling” to his own counseling practice,
Marinoff’s approach has nothing in common with Achenbach’s. Additionally, Marinoff distorts
the history of philosophical counseling in the USA: In 1995, I read a paper at the American
Philosophers Association, in a special session sponsored by the American Society for
Philosophy, Counseling, and Psychotherapy, in New York. This gave me the opportunity to
interview (and I kept the recordings of these interviews) some of the USA pioneers of
philosophical counseling, e.g. Professor Elliot Cohen and Professor Paul Sharkey. They both said
that at that stage no philosopher in the USA had hung out a shingle with the name “Philosophical
Counselor,” but they were preparing and organizing themselves to begin this new type of
counseling as professionally as possible. Both philosophers had been working in other
institutional frameworks (respectively, in psychotherapy, and as an ethical consultant in a
hospital), jobs that they felt had something in common with that of the philosophical counselor,
but no more than that. Nevertheless, in Philosophical Practice Marinoff names Professor
Sharkey and other USA philosophers and psychotherapists as early pioneers and visionaries of
contemporary philosophical practice, i.e. as if they were predecessors of Achenbach(p. 68, and
Marinoff – and presumably his APPA organization as well – makes inappropriate use of
the term “therapy” as applied to philosophical counseling. He claims to have discovered the new
meaning of this term, which is simply a reversion to one of its old etymological senses: “to
attend to”. (Plato, Not Prozac, pp. 35, 36, and Philosophical Practice, pp. 84 and 85). This
etymological word game seems good enough to him to turn many kinds of “attending” activities
into therapy. His “attending” to his clients’ problems is therapy, my “attending” to his books as
a critical reviewer is without doubt therapy, and the finance minister attendingto the financial
affairs of his country is practicing therapy and so on.
Gerd Achenbach and most of the European practitioners began practicing philosophy as
an alternative to psychotherapy and psychoanalysis, but this is not a kind of therapy.1 Early in his
counseling career, Achenbach produced two books, Philosopische Praxis, and Das Prinzip Heilung, with elementary outlines that became stepping stones in the practice of many beginning
philosophical counselors. Yet, in Plato, not Prozac, Marinoff claims that no two philosophical
counselors’ work is methodologically alike: "philosophical counseling has at least as many
permutations as there are practitioners" (p. 37). But in Philosophical Practice, he says that there
are 3 types of philosophical counseling dialogue, and that his own original method (type A) is
also the basis of Achenbach’s “spontaneous” manner of counseling, i.e. without any particular
method (pp. 87-90). Marinoff’s one-sentence descriptions of Achenbach’s open-ended method
are mistaken and misleading. Achenbach is not spontaneous in the sense that his way of
philosophical counseling is without any methodological content. The basic points that
Achenbach presented for philosophical counseling are: 1. Sincere communication between the
philosophical practitioner (an academically trained philosopher) and the visitor or client, based
on a "beyond-method" method. 2. The importance of dialogue, as that which enlivens and flows
from being. 3. "Auslegen" – a looking for explanations – in which the practitioner becomes
united with the problem, not by imparting his own understanding of it, but by giving the visitor a
fresh impulse to explain him or herself. This instead of “ünterlegen” – explanations given by
psychotherapists (or others!) to their patients’s problems. 4. The innovative component of
dialogue, the element of wonder in philosophical practice, which does not allow for fixed
viewpoints, standard attitudes or permanent solutions.2 Consequently, philosophical counseling
is not about applying philosophy, as if placing a poultice of Kant on the soul, but it is
Marinoff’s two approaches of applying philosophy, “PEACE” and “MEANS” are
antithetical to any “spontaneous manner of counseling” or Achenbach’s outline for practice. The
MEANS method is presented in the last chapter of Therapy for the Sane. It is an approach
towards examining one’s life philosophically, and it includes some exercises. The acronym
stands for Moments of truth, Expectations, Attachments, Negative emotions, and Sagacious
choices. As in Marinoff’s first two books, the therapeutic goal here is apparently inspired by
Buddhist, meditative, and spiritual sources, which he combines with the philosophy of Hobbes,
Ayn Rand, and others. Hobbes is admired as the greatest philosopher since Aristotle! Unlike
Marinoff’s New Age cocktail, Achenbach’s practice is derived from modernist, critical, and
skeptical sources, and philosophizing with the client remains the ultimate goal of the practice.
Marinoff considers that the three first stages of his PEACE process are equivalent to what
persons usually do autonomously, or in psychological therapy. Only the last two stages are
philosophy (Plato, not Prozac, pp. 38, 39, 42). But a few pages further (on page 44) he writes
that "the third and the fourth steps – analysis and contemplation – distinguish this method from
what has gone before." His initial claim that psychotherapy is about identifying a particular
problem for which a person goes into therapy, about expressing the emotions that relate to this
problem, and then finally analyzing the options to solve this problem, can only be based on
inadequate knowledge of how most psychologists and psychotherapist, work. It is also surprising
that although Marinoff vigorously attacks the DSM-IV and the superfluous use of psychoactive
drugs, he seems unaware that not only do psychiatrists work with diagnostic manuals and believe
in drug therapy, but most mental health practitioners also employ the DSM and condone the use
of drugs in many cases. Yet, there are a few instances were Marinoff names psychologists as
well as "experts at reifying syndromes and disorders," however the split he indicated between
psychiatry and psychology is not much consolidated by these common applications of the DSM
(Plato, Not Prozac, pp. 19, 20, 30, 32, 34).
Marinoff’s misapplication of the term “philosophy” is also quite problematic: for
example in Plato, not Prozac (p. 39) “contemplation” is considered philosophizing, inPhilosophical Practice (p. 62) “meditation” is philosophizing. However, in the history of
philosophy one finds that the terms “contemplation” and “meditation” seldom appear, and when
they do, these terms are mainly used to mark theological and mystical kinds of philosophy. For
example, Thomas Merton, one of the first and the most famous Catholic clergymen engaged with
Buddhism, wrote in The New Man: "Contemplation is a mystery in which God reveals Himself
as the very center of our own inmost self, intimior intimo meo as St. Augustine said."3 In the
Catholic tradition contemplative prayer and the contemplative life have had for many ages, and
still have, a similar function as meditation in the religious traditions of the Far East. Meditation
as philosophy is usually that type of philosophy in which the philosopher observes and reflects
on his own mind, for example the Meditations of Marcus Aurelius and Descartes. But most
philosophy is profoundly non-contemplative and non-meditative in character because of its
argumentative nature and dialectic attitudes. For Marinoff meditation has two “meanings”
(stages), an active and passive one. The first is philosophy as taught in colleges (“it entails the
thoughts of all the great philosophers”), the second is that kind of meditation associated with the
drug culture of the 1960’s—anything that alters and expands consciousness: it is "inactive
meditation, or bringing the mind to a quiescent state" (Philosophy Practice pp. 62-63).
Personally Marinoff prefers meditation that has its roots in the ancient Far East, as he quotes
abundantly Chinese and Zen sages. For example, his citation of Lao Tzu: “the Sage carries on
his business without action, and gives his teaching without words. He governs by non-action;
consequently there is nothing ungoverned” (Philosophy Practice, pp. 63).
Marinoff perceives himself as a kind of mystic; he asks his readers to call him "a mystical
pragmatist" (Plato, Not Prozac, p. 304), in addition he calls himself the 21st century Hobbes, and
compares himself to Julius Caesar (Philosophy Practice, pp. xxiii, 243). As Caesar, Marinoff
believes that he –- actually, he addresses himself here in the first person plural pronoun, or
possibly he includes in his "we" his APPA membership combatants -- will be victorious on the
battlefield, i.e. in his battles for the sake of legislating philosophical practice. Marinoff envisions
as his enemies all those highly qualified professional philosophers, counselors, and other
academics, which oppose his persistent attempts at licensing philosophers. He calls his
opponents charlatans and amateurs. (Philosophy Practice, pp. 227, 243, 244).
Yet, Marinoff encourages the application of any school of thought, and as in most New
Ages approaches, critical reasoning is absent. Madame Blavatsky, Bhagwan Sri Rajneesh,
Chogyam Trungpa, and other dubious and esoteric thinkers, are described as meaningful thinkers
for philosophical counseling sessions and self-help. Marinoff even advises his readers and clients
to visit gurus and astrologers without exercising any philosophical discrimination (Therapy for the Sane, p. 7, Plato, not Prozac, p. 54). This advice seems to be grounded in his own perception
of pragmatism: "If something's good for you, it's good" (Plato, not Prozac, p. 72). Marinoff
himself has practiced I Ching for more than thirty years and helps his counselees and readers to
get acquainted with this ancient Chinese method of "philosophical counseling": “The coins may
simply even out the odds. But no matter which chapter you hit, your active conscious mind will
find something meaningful and useful in the text, which is actually a reflection of what is
meaningful and useful in your submerged thoughts. There will be a resonance between its
wisdom and yours, for the I Ching mirrors what is in your heart” (Plato, not Prozac, p. 301). So
far, in all his books are sections explaining the I Ching, and case studies in which the I Ching is
the chosen instrument of therapy. However, one cannot consider, as Marinoff does, Chinese
philosophy to consist mainly of Confucianism, Taoism, and the I Ching, and one cannot claim
that Chinese philosophy has as its central tenet “that everything changes” (Plato, not Prozac, p.
In Therapy for the Sane, the title and main question of Chapter 10 is “Are you a spiritual
being?” And as in the other chapters of this book the therapist has an answer at hand. The answer
in this chapter is given immediately, in the first sentence of the chapter: “If you neglect, ignore,
or deny the spiritual aspects of your being, you will fail to live life as fully as possible. And that
can produce dis-ease and disease alike” (p. 262). Accordingly, although it seems that Marinoff
does not consign the unspiritual minded to the flames of an eternal hell, he nevertheless
envisions secular people as a kind of invalid, invoking through their unspiritual living dis-ease
and disease on themselves; or in other words, hell on earth!
I personally appreciate Marinoff’s quest for spirituality, but his predictive warnings, even
if well intended, are no positive encouragement to spirituality, nor are his predictions necessarily
Why would the type of practical spiritual guidance that Marinoff advocates, be a part of
philosophical counseling? Especially if the philosophical counselor is not an expert in these
matters like the professionally educated spiritual director, or pastoral counselor. Usually spiritual
guidance is given by priests, pastors, rabbis, and like religious leaders. Philosophical
practitioners with adequate knowledge in the areas of religion, spirituality, or mysticism, can
philosophize with their clients on these matters, but should take care not to lower themselves to
Most philosophical counselors worldwide are not very enthusiastic about Plato, not Prozac, to put it mildly.4 Neither are Philosophical Practice, and Therapy for the Sane, more
appreciated.5 Yet, there have been some philosophical counselors and psychotherapists who
appear untroubled by Marinoff’s errors in historical-philosophical facts, his curious arguments,
contradictions, irrational guidance, and the banality of method and superficial examples, and
these will praise Plato, not Prozac, and his other writings.6 However, Marinoff’s many errors
These and additional reviews only present a limited number of Marinoff’s errors. I found
other mistakes in Plato, Not Prozac and in Therapy for the Sane in the sections entitled “Hit
Parade of Philosophers” and the “Hit Parade of Ideas,” where over fifty philosophers are
sketched. Among these Marinoff mentions St. Augustine as having invented the doctrine of
original sin (Plato, Not Prozac, p. 275 and, Therapy for the Sane, p. 339). However, Augustine
may have coined the phrase “original sin”, but he could not possibly have invented the idea or
the doctrine of such sin. The idea that human beings are born in sin is not Augustine’s invention;
the idea’s origin can be traced, for example, to Hindu scriptures, to the Bible, and the Talmud.
Marinoff most of all errs when he writes about religion, in particular, about the relation
between philosophy and theology. Since Philo, around the beginning of 1st century, and ever
after, Western philosophy has been the “lowly handmaiden,” if not the lover of theology.
Evidence thereof is found in Judaism, Christianity, and later also in the Muslim tradition. Also
the Far East religious traditions have their great theological philosophers. Theologians defined
the alliance between the two professions often differently. Only a few of the early Church
fathers, e.g. St. Jerome, rejected all philosophy as vain deception. However, through St. Ambrose
and St. Augustine philosophy became a valuable tool for Christian theology. Nevertheless, in
Marinoff’s view the history of philosophy looks different. He defines the relationship between
philosophy and theology as fundamentally opposed: “theology, which requires faith, and
philosophy, which requires doubt, often makes the two fields incompatible, as they certainly
were for more than a millennium, until the Reformation and the eventual beginning of the
Scientific Revolution” (Plato, Not Prozac, p. 60). Thus, Marinoff omits from the history of
philosophy the ages of Scholastic glory. One may not agree with, or one even may dislike the
Scholastic tradition, but one cannot say that the Doctors of the Church were not doing
In the light of all the errors referred to so far, I cannot recommend Marinoff’s writings as
textbooks for colleges, or as profitable reading material for the philosophically uneducated; nor
are they suitable for philosophical counselors, psychotherapists, and others. Still, there are
people who believe that popularizing erroneous knowledge about philosophical counseling--or
other areas--is to be preferred over no knowledge. Fortunately, there are also a number of books
on the market that give the reader a better, or even an excellent understanding of this new
profession in philosophy. And, indeed, if a novice in philosophy wants to apply philosophical
ideas, or wisdom to his life, I suggest reading Bertrand Russell’s Wisdom of the West or just any
good contemporary introduction to philosophy. Through these books, and not through
Marinoff’s, a person is likely to benefit more.
Endnotes
1 Achenbach, Gerd B. Philosophische Praxis. Cologne: Jürgen Dinter, 1984. Achenbach, Gerd B. & Thomas Macho. Das Prinzip Heilung. Cologne: Jürgen Dinter, 1985. 2 Shlomit C. Schuster, Philosophy Practice: An Alternative to Counseling and Psychotherapy, Westport, Conn.: Praeger Publishers, 1999, pp. 34 - 42.
3 Thomas Merton, The New Man, New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1999, p. 19. 4 Many of my colleagues in Europe, Israel, and the USA-- including members of APPA-- which I met at conferences, or am in contact with through email, told me about their "disappointment," or even "disgust," with Marinoff's books. But most of these colleagues will not say so publicly. When Marinoff is challenged in public, as for example at the 2004 conference in Seville, he does not answers to questions or comments, or at another occasion his reply to criticism was: "I have written a best seller, so it is natural that such criticism should arise." (In the Hebrew weekly Mekor Rishon, <http://www.geocities.com/centersophon/mikorishon.html>, last accessed 31.1.2005). 5 Ibid. 6 For example see the reviews of Alex Howard, Christian Perring, and Ben Mulvey, at The Metapsychology Online Book Reviews Website <http://www.mentalhelp.net/books> (last accessed 31.1.2005), or Paul W. Sharkey's Foreword to Marinoff's Philosophical Practice, pp. xv-xviii. 7 For example see Daniel Duane’s article “The Socratic Shrink” in The New York Times Magazine (March 21, 2004), Peter B. Raabe’s review of Philosophical Practice in Practical Philosophy (Spring 2002, Vol. 4.2) <http://www.practical-philosophy.org.uk> (last accessed 31.1.2005), Roger Scruton’s “The Return of the Sophist”, in The Times (London, 11 August 1997), Alessandro Volpone’s “Plato, Not Viagra! The Comedy of Errors May be Continued” <http://www.geocities.com/centersophon/PlatoNotViagra.html> (last accessed 31.1.2005), and Tudor B. Munteanu’s review of Plato, not Prozac! <http://www.friesian.com/munteanu.htm> (last accessed 31.1.2005).
Living Water International Advanced Participatory Hygiene Lesson Malaria & Dengue Fever Message: • Malaria, Dengue Fevers kill many people each year. Knowing the signs and symptoms • Proper care of someone with a fever may make the difference between life and death Background: Insects are part of our environment, the natural world around us. They are affected by